Search

The Huxley Agnostic

agnostic, agnosticism

Addled Atheists: Binary Bullshit

I’ll quickly clarify that I agree things work in a binary fashion. What is bullshit, though, is the way a-theists do things.

An objective truth claim gives us the first binary. Objectively, X is true or X is false, X or ~X. Subjectively, you can believe either of those as soon as a claim is on the table. But, you can also have no belief, either way.

Claim: X

Do you believe X is true?
Do you believe X is false?

YN: belief X is true, no belief X is false
NN: no belief X is true, no belief X is false
NY: no belief X is true, belief X is false

While NN does share “no belief X is true” with NY, it also shares “no belief X is false” with YN. NN shares a “no belief” with both and doesn’t share either of their “belief”. Those are 3 distinct positions of belief/non-belief.

What a-theists like to do, rather than presenting the claim and asking if you believe it’s true or false, is present a belief the claim is true, and ask if you have that belief, or not. Based on their dictating that single question, ignoring whether anyone believes the claim is false, they get the results they want. They claim those are the only two options. That’s just not true, as I’ve shown already. Those are just the only two options they’re presenting.

Do you believe X is true?

Y: belief X is true
N: no belief X is true

That’s just arbitrarily permanently grouping NN and NY, as if they’re the same thing, when they’re clearly not the same thing. Yes, NN and NY are both non-YNs. But, YN and NN are both non-NYs. And, YN and NY are both non-NNs. There may be reasons to temporarily group them for discussion, but no real reason to permanently group them.

A-theists carry their faulty binary system over into all the 4 position models floating around the internet. They’re all garbage. They are more dishonest than dictating a single belief question, because they actually include the X is false counter claim, yet they still ignore beliefs about it.

Do you believe X is true?
Do you “know” X is true?
Do you “know” X is false?

YYN: b(elief):X|k(nowledge):X|~k(nowledge):~X
YNN: b:X|~k:X|~k:~X
NNN: ~b:X|~k:X|~k:~X
NNY: ~b:X|~k:X|k:~X

You only get 4 position by dishonestly ignoring beliefs about “X is false”, even though you’ve clearly acknowledged the counter claim exists in your 4 positions. If you include a belief question about “X is false”, you get 5 positions.

Do you believe X is true?
Do you believe X is false?
Do you “know” X is true?
Do you “know” X is false?

YNYN: b:X|~b:~X|k:X|~k:~X
YNNN: b:X|~b:~X|~k:X|~k:~X
NNNN: ~b:X|~b:~X|~k:X|~k:~X
NYNN: ~b:X|b:~X|~k:X|~k:~X
NYNY: ~b:X|b:~X|~k:X|k:~X

Based on their binary bullshit, a-theists claim there is no middle. In actual fact, they’re dishonestly calling the NN or NNNN middle “atheist”, along with NY, NYNN, and NYNY. They dictate things the way they want, to get the results they want, based on dogmatically sticking with a preconceived definition of “atheist”. Whatever terminology you prefer to use, 2 and 4 positions is just absolute garbage.

~P + ist = someone who believes “not P”
~ + Pist = not someone who believes “P”

Both make the word ~Pist, but the first is the way the word was put together. NN is not a ~P + ist.

Advertisements

Why Sam Harris is a Moron, Part 3: Appeals to Emotion & Thought Experiments

Sam is obviously very good at remaining calm and talking in a very soothing, monotone, manner. However, if you read transcripts of what he’s saying, you realize that he repeatedly relies on appeals to emotion.

Regarding his “objective” morality:

So, I’m going to argue that this is an illusion — that the separation between science and human values is an illusion — and actually quite a dangerous one at this point in human history.

Whether it is “dangerous”, or not, is totally irrelevant to whether he has actually presented us with objective morality, or not. Just a calmly stated scare tactic, to try and get people to accept his nonsense.

For instance, there are 21 states in our country where corporal punishment in the classroom is legal, where it is legal for a teacher to beat a child with a wooden board, hard, and raising large bruises and blisters and even breaking the skin.

This is exactly the same kind of appeals to emotion that countless other “objective” moralists present to people. A favourite is torturing babies for fun. Feelings will stir within the vast majority of people, thinking of babies and children being abused. The very fact that they’re relying on an emotional reaction, however, clearly indicates these examples are directed at peoples subjectivity. Sam, and the others, then try to pass of this near unanimous subjective agreement, intersubjectivity, as objectivity. But, that’s just not how objectivity works.

Relying on empirical senses is objectivity. That everyone in a room agrees they see, smell, feel, maybe even taste, an object and concludes it is a flower means that there appears to be a flower there, independent of any individual subject’s senses, therefore independent of all the subjects’ senses. On the other hand, that everyone in the room also agrees that it is a pretty flower is dependent on every subject’s subjective opinion about the flower. That it is pretty is simply subjective agreement. Just like if everyone in a movie theatre thought the movie was great, everyone at an art gallery thought the art was fantastic, or everyone in a pizzeria thought that they made the best pizza.

The fact that Sam has to rely on these types of appeals to emotion, is actually more evidence his “objective” morality is anything but. A truly objective argument should be able to avoid such things.

Now, it is the position, generally speaking, of our intellectual community that while we may not like this, we might think of this as “wrong” in Boston or Palo Alto, who are we to say that the proud denizens of an ancient culture are wrong to force their wives and daughters to live in cloth bags? And who are we to say, even, that they’re wrong to beat them with lengths of steel cable, or throw battery acid in their faces if they decline the privilege of being smothered in this way?

Again with extreme examples, to appeal to the audience’s emotions, in an effort to push them in the direction of agreeing with what is being said. This shouldn’t be included in an objective argument. I don’t argue objective morality, so think about a loved one. Would you do just about anything to protect them from harm? Think about that loved one committing what you consider to be the most immoral thing they could possibly do. Would you do just about anything to stop them? Almost everyone might answer “Yes” to both of those questions. You might not agree with their methods, and might not agree with them about what they need to be protected against, but you still might agree with their general thought process. I can subjectively disagree with their methods and reasons all I want. But, if you’re arguing objectivity, there should be an objective way to tell whether their reasoning and/or methods are objectively right, or wrong. without the appeals to emotion.

But what does voluntary mean in a community where, when a girl gets raped, her father’s first impulse, rather often, is to murder her out of shame?

More appeals to emotion, to back an “objective” argument. We are presented moral thought experiments all the time, in fiction we read, or watch. There are a number of stories where the parent puts their own child out of their misery, or kills their own child before a worse fate is about to happen, and it is presented as the moral thing to do. Or, at least, reasonable. We may disagree with what is, or isn’t, a worse fate, or what level of misery is, or isn’t, worth putting them out of their misery, but we have been presented with similar thought experiments from the parent’s perspective, and have been led to feel that it was an okay thing to do.

TV Tropes: Mercy Kill

Just a note on the “rather often”, as well. If you consider how horrifyingly often girls and women get raped, especially in war torn areas, and the number of times you actually hear about women being killed by their families or government after being raped, “rather often” would seem to actually mean rarely, unless there’s evidence otherwise. You also hear reports like that of a girl who was raped in Afghanistan. The local imam took care of her until her father returned home, and the father then traveled for days with her to the nearest hospital.

Now the irony, from my perspective, is that the only people who seem to generally agree with me and who think that there are right and wrong answers to moral questions are religious demagogues of one form or another.

But the demagogues are right about one thing: We need a universal conception of human values.

Another appeal to emotion. Whether I feel the “need” to know if the earth is round, or not, is irrelevant to whether it objectively is, or not. Whether everyone universally accepts that the earth is round is irrelevant to whether it objectively is, or not.

There are more examples from his objective morality argument, but here are some examples from other arguments:

Imagine that a known terrorist has planted a bomb in the heart of a nearby city. He now sits in your custody. Rather than conceal his guilt, he gloats about the forthcoming explosion and the magnitude of human suffering it will cause. Given this state of affairs—in particular, given that there is still time to prevent an imminent atrocity—it seems that subjecting this unpleasant fellow to torture may be justifiable.

Here, our “objectively” moral Sam Harris is justifying torture. It’s an extreme trolley car thought experiment, designed to elicit an emotional reaction. There is no objectively right or wrong answer to a trolley car scenario. There’s just the results of what most people tend to choose and what most people don’t tend to choose. The results don’t indicate objectivity any more than observing what pizza toppings people tend to choose indicates objectivity.

“In 2007, the psychologists Fiery Cushman and Liane Young and the biologist Marc Hauser administered the test to thousands of web users and found that while 89 percent would flip the track switch, only about 11 percent would push the fat man.”

“That contradiction—that people find giving the man a fatal prod just too disturbing, even though the end result would be the same—is supposed to show how emotions can sometimes color our ethical judgments.”

Is One of the Most Popular Psychology Experiments Worthless?

Sam might be in the 11 percent that does it, either way, but most people don’t actually seem to want to get hands on. They’re okay with the seemingly non-violent act of flipping a switch, but not okay with hands on murder. As with his morality, Sam “ironically” (not so ironic when it becomes habit) lands on the side of religious demagogues. More of the Republican, Christian Right, support torture, than other groups, when surveyed. Sam’s own moral argument should make torturing someone objectively morally wrong. So, now he’s effectively arguing that doing what is objectively morally wrong is what we ought to do, which would seem to contradict an objective “ought not do” included in considering something morally wrong. His argument becomes partly gibberish … torture is something we ought not do that we ought to do … and partly relative … under certain circumstances.

It should be of particular concern to us that the beliefs of Muslims pose a special problem for nuclear deterrence. There is little possibility of our having a cold war with an Islamist regime armed with long-range nuclear weapons. A cold war requires that the parties be mutually deterred by the threat of death. Notions of martyrdom and jihad run roughshod over the logic that allowed the United States and the Soviet Union to pass half a century perched, more or less stably, on the brink of Armageddon. What will we do if an Islamist regime, which grows dewy-eyed at the mere mention of paradise, ever acquires long-range nuclear weaponry? If history is any guide, we will not be sure about where the offending warheads are or what their state of readiness is, and so we will be unable to rely on targeted, conventional weapons to destroy them. In such a situation, the only thing likely to ensure our survival may be a nuclear first strike of our own.

OMG! What if Muslims get nuclear weapons?! Like Pakistan? Whose government he has described as Islamist? Push the button! Another extreme example to elicit emotional reactions, which he then relies on to sound reasonable. He’s not. He’s insane. Sam Harris should never be allowed to run a country, or be any kind of adviser to someone running a country.

Not only is this an extreme appeal to emotion, it shows one of Sam’s less nuanced discussions about Muslims. He flows swiftly from “Muslim” to suicidal “Jihadist” in the blink of an eye. The beliefs of “Muslims” isn’t really a problem, because most are opposed to terrorism and using violence against innocent people. But, sure, some Muslims might be dangerous. Fortunately, most Muslims don’t like those dangerous Muslims either.

One of the things that makes Sam dangerously insane is that he has no clue how “nuclear deterrence” works. It is based on mutually assured destruction. Before your nuclear weapons can hit them, they can send theirs to hit you. Starting a nuclear war is suicidal. It only worked in Japan because they didn’t have any to fire back. Sam just imagines that he has successfully nuked them without them firing back, and wonders what the rest of the world will think. They’ll think you’re dumber than a stump is what they’ll think. Not to defend the actions of terrorists, but what also makes Sam insane is whole thought process is based on totally delusional lies that he has convinced himself with. The upper levels of terrorist organizations tend to have goals they want to live to see achieved. ISIS wants to bring about another Caliphate, an Islamic Empire. Kind of hard to do, if you’re all dead. They aren’t suicidal as a whole group. It’s only low level dimwits that they convince to kill themselves for the cause. Sam, the “expert” on Islam, and Muslim extremists, doesn’t even grasp some very basic facts.

I’m going to talk about a failure of intuition that many of us suffer from. It’s really a failure to detect a certain kind of danger. I’m going to describe a scenario that I think is both terrifying and likely to occur, and that’s not a good combination, as it turns out. And yet rather than be scared, most of you will feel that what I’m talking about is kind of cool.

I’m going to describe how the gains we make in artificial intelligence could ultimately destroy us. And in fact, I think it’s very difficult to see how they won’t destroy us or inspire us to destroy ourselves.

After all these sci-fi stories about robots, electronics, computers, taking over the world, we will still be “likely” to make them without an off switch? He doesn’t even think we have free will, but somehow we’re going to make supercomputers that can totally decide to do whatever they want. Complete subjective freedom. The danger is actually in the programmer. Thankfully most programmers don’t consider themselves to be Dr Evil.

The concern is really that we will build machines that are so much more competent than we are that the slightest divergence between their goals and our own could destroy us.

Just think about how we relate to ants. We don’t hate them. We don’t go out of our way to harm them. In fact, sometimes we take pains not to harm them. We step over them on the sidewalk. But whenever their presence seriously conflicts with one of our goals, let’s say when constructing a building like this one, we annihilate them without a qualm. The concern is that we will one day build machines that, whether they’re conscious or not, could treat us with similar disregard.

More appeals to emotion. I’m not sure why Sam is so concerned. In his “objective” morality argument, he described an “objective” hierarchy of beings, with the most intelligent and aware at the top. If the AI is to us as we are to ants, then it should “objectively” have more value, if Sam is consistent. He’s not. He is still concerned primarily with humans. If the AI decided that wiping out humans would increase the “well being” of all AIs, or the “well being” of most conscious creatures, descided humans were like a virus, or plague on the planet, then wouldn’t the AI be “objectively” morally in the right, to do so? That would put us, trying to stay alive, “objectively” morally in the wrong. It is quite obvious that Sam’s hierarchy was completely subjective and that he has an emotional attachment to humans, over all others. He’s a very emotional guy, albeit a calm, monotone, one.

Why Sam Harris is a Moron, Part 2: Objective Morality

Someone actually gave Sam a PhD, for his moral landscape thesis. I hope all the universities aren’t giving out PhDs for theses based on not knowing the definition of a word. The word Sam doesn’t seem to know the definition of is “objective”.

Science can answer moral questions

I’m going to speak today about the relationship between science and human values. Now, it’s generally understood that questions of morality — questions of good and evil and right and wrong — are questions about which science officially has no opinion. It’s thought that science can help us get what we value, but it can never tell us what we ought to value. And, consequently, most people — I think most people probably here — think that science will never answer the most important questions in human life: questions like, “What is worth living for?” “What is worth dying for?” “What constitutes a good life?”
So, I’m going to argue that this is an illusion — that the separation between science and human values is an illusion — and actually quite a dangerous one at this point in human history.

Some of Sam’s fans have the strange notion that Sam is only arguing that science can be used to help us reach moral decisions. But, as he clearly states here, Sam acknowledges that people already use science in such a way. I’ve never heard anyone argue that you can’t use science in such a way. So, no, that is not the gist of Sam’s argument. That would be a Captain Obvious line of argument, that would deserve little attention, and would be even less worthy of a PhD. What he is setting out to do, “the separation between science and human values is an illusion”, is to argue that you can get an “ought” from an “is”. He laughingly thinks he has solved the is/ought problem.

In case you haven’t heard of the is/ought problem before…

The Is / Ought Problem

How does Sam manage to bridge this gap? Through make believe, is how he does it.

Well being is not new concept, but Sam likes to pretend that he has found the perfect objective definition for “well being”. And, if you don’t believe him, well then, you’re an “imbecile”.

Now, many of you might worry that the notion of well-being is truly undefined, and seemingly perpetually open to be re-construed. And so, how therefore can there be an objective notion of well-being? Well, consider by analogy, the concept of physical health.

Okay, let’s consider the concept of physical health. Science can show us that, if you do what is healthy, and avoid what is unhealthy, then you have a better chance of living longer. So what? I also have a better chance of living longer if I never go sky diving. That doesn’t mean I ought to never go sky diving. Science will also show us that, if we find a cure for all sickness, disease, and aging, that we will likely have a serious population problem on our hands. Nowhere does science tell us that we ought to prolong the lives of as many people for as long as possible. That’s just something we decide to do, all on our own because we, as individuals, would like to live as long as possible.

Science doesn’t actually care about you, or me, one little bit. While science can show that someone is riddled with cancer it, in no way, tells us what we ought to do about it. I could just as easily use facts to support putting them out of their misery immediately, as I could to support prolonging their lives as long as possible. It would reduce suffering and save money, if we just put them down, as quickly as possible. I could use that argument to put down a lot of people, which is the slippery slope that led to Social Darwinism or euthenasia which some of Sam’s critics have previously mentioned. Sam just ad homs those arguments away, without taking them seriously.

Well think of how we talk about food: I would never be tempted to argue to you that there must be one right food to eat. There is clearly a range of materials that constitute healthy food. But there’s nevertheless a clear distinction between food and poison.

Sam seems to be suggesting that we ought to avoid putting poisons into our bodies. This is a very strange notion. I’m glad he’s not an actual medical doctor. I take it Sam has never heard of treatments for cancer, or that death due to over-dosing is listed as death due to poisoning, by the CDC. We put “poisons” into our bodies constantly. You are only actually “poisoned”, if you take too much of something. Aside from drugs and alcohol, you can also “poison” yourself with things like caffeine, and black licorice. You can even “poison” yourself to death with too much water. I would hope Sam doesn’t suggest that everyone avoids water.

At best, we can objectively state that, if you put X amount of substance A into your body, you will likely die. Now, if you don’t want to die, then it might seem obvious that you ought not do that. But, what if dying, or killing, is exactly what you want to do? Some places that have deemed capital punishment a valid punishment for certain crimes, poison people to death. Sometimes we are in favour of compassionate assisted suicide and poison people to death. If we bend the rules for certain things, does it cancel out any objectiveness? I’d say yes. I’d say the end goal is relative to the situation.

According to Sam, the answer is no. He believes you actually can bend “objectivity” all you want. Another very strange notion…

Consider, by analogy, the game of chess. Now, if you’re going to play good chess, a principle like, “Don’t lose your Queen,” is very good to follow. But it clearly admits some exceptions. There are moments when losing your Queen is a brilliant thing to do. There are moments when it is the only good thing you can do. And yet, chess is a domain of perfect objectivity. The fact that there are exceptions here does not change that at all.

What actually is objective, about chess? The board is 8 squares by 8 squares. A certain piece is allowed to move in a certain way. If your king is captured, you lose the game. And, that’s about it. A good principle is not objective, at all. What you ought to, and ought not, do is totally relative to your goal, and the situation you are in. Even winning being the goal isn’t “objective”. If you are playing your child, and want to let them win, then you ought to let your king be captured. If you’re in a situation where you believe the best move is to lose your queen, then you ought to lose your queen. There is no “perfect objectivity” to chess. You make your move relative to the situation you are in, and relative to your end goal.

Sam seems to have a serious problem understanding, exactly, what “objective” means. It should mean that something is true, independent of a mind. Something that is true should always remain true. If a mind is deciding that something is true sometimes, but false at other times, to suit them, then that something should not be considered “objective”.

Now, this brings us to the sorts of moves that people are apt to make in the moral sphere. Consider the great problem of women’s bodies: What to do about them? Well this is one thing you can do about them: You can cover them up. Now, it is the position, generally speaking, of our intellectual community that while we may not like this, we might think of this as “wrong” in Boston or Palo Alto, who are we to say that the proud denizens of an ancient culture are wrong to force their wives and daughters to live in cloth bags? And who are we to say, even, that they’re wrong to beat them with lengths of steel cable, or throw battery acid in their faces if they decline the privilege of being smothered in this way?

Sam likes thought experiments, so let us imagine that someone we love is doing something that almost anyone on the planet would consider immoral…something absolutely vile, disgusting, horrid. You can pick the worst think in your own mind. Now, would it be an “objective” fact that we ought not hurt said loved one, in an attempt to stop them? I don’t know about anyone else, but I can think of reasons why I might hurt, or even kill, someone I love, in an attempt to stop them from doing the unthinkable (molesting a child is my pick for the worst). So, I don’t see the “objective” ought not beat, harm, or even kill someone you care about, should the worst be happening.

Again, we’re faced with a subjective and relative judgement. In my personal opinion, a wife or daughter going out whenever they want, wearing whatever they want, shouldn’t be grounds for resorting to such extreme behaviour. Someone else might consider those things terrible. There is no “objective” truth, here. If I want them to change, I have to convince them of the validity of my truth. Or, if we both change a bit, we might be able to come to some kind of subjective consensus about what is, and isn’t, acceptable, that we can both live with. That’s how the democratic process works. If there were objective, scientifically demonstrable, moral truths we wouldn’t need democracies.

Now the irony, from my perspective, is that the only people who seem to generally agree with me and who think that there are right and wrong answers to moral questions are religious demagogues of one form or another.
But the demagogues are right about one thing: We need a universal conception of human values.

This “irony” becomes somewhat less ironic the more Sam’s arguments land him on the side of religious demagogues. It’s becoming expected. While “we need” is a swell appeal to emotion, it won’t make your argument any more true. Sam has provided zero evidence of any kind of objective morality.

Now, what stands in the way of this? Well, one thing to notice is that we do something different when talking about morality — especially secular, academic, scientist types. When talking about morality we value differences of opinion in a way that we don’t in any other area of our lives. So, for instance the Dalai Lama gets up every morning meditating on compassion, and he thinks that helping other human beings is an integral component of human happiness. On the other hand, we have someone like Ted Bundy; Ted Bundy was very fond of abducting and raping and torturing and killing young women.

Sam goes on to suggest that we can just discard moral opinions that we don’t agree with, just like we can discard the opinions of scientists who aren’t specialists in the field we’re discussing. Now, is science going to tell us which voices we can discard? According to my science, we can discard the opinions of someone who justifies torture, justifies more guns, justifies financial support of the worst Islamist country in the world, justifies a nuclear first strike, justifies profiling, justifies fear mongering, etc. By Sam’s own “logic”, I say we can discard The Moral Landscape, and all opinions on morality, presented by such a morally inept person.

Why Sam Harris is a Moron, Part 1: Islamophobia

It is hard to know where to begin, with Sam Harris. He is so addled, that it’s going to take multiple posts to describe just how addled he is. Let’s start with Islamophobia.

When I recently asked Sam Harris what he thought of the word ‘Islamophobia,’ he directed me to a tweet that noted the following: “Islamophobia. A word created by fascists, & used by cowards, to manipulate morons.”
“I don’t think [the tweet] overstates the case by much,” said Harris

You know, one thing I’d expect a neuroscientist to have somewhat of an expert opinion on is phobias. Yet, Sam Harris constantly rejects Islamophobia as not a thing. To argue that it doesn’t apply to you, and describing why it doesn’t apply to you, or describing why it doesn’t apply to certain criticisms, would be a valid line of argument. However, to just suggest it doesn’t exist, is moronic nonsense.

Arachnophobia: In a basic sense, arachnophobia is an irrational fear, or hatred, of spiders. Yes, some spiders are very dangerous, and some will try to kill you. But, to have a fear of all spiders is quite irrational.

Islamophobia: Likewise, an irrational fear, or hatred, of Muslims, or anything Islamic. Yes, some Muslims are very dangerous, and some will try to kill you. But, to have a fear of all Muslims is quite irrational.

To argue that there are no people that have an irrational fear of all Muslims, or anything Islamic, is utter nonsense. Even if only one person in the world was afflicted with it, it would still be a thing. People standing outside a mosque with automatic weapons aren’t doing it out of bravery. They’re doing it out of fear. These tough guys, can actually be considered chicken shits. They’re truly scared to death.

islamophobe1
Another way to look at is that, like racism and sexism are specific kinds of bigotry, a number of phobias can be seen as specific kinds of xenophobia. Some specific things seem so strange, or foreign, to some people’s minds, that they form an irrational fear, or hatred, of it.

Xenophobia: an unreasonable fear or hatred of foreigners or strangers or of that which is foreign or strange

Homophobia: an unreasonable fear or hatred of homosexuals or of that which has to do with homosexuality

Judeophobia: an unreasonable fear or hatred of Jews or of that which has to do with Judaism or anything Jewish

Islamophobia: an unreasonable fear or hatred of Muslims or of that which has to do with Islam or anything Islamic

For Sam Harris to just outright deny the existence of Islamophobia indicates he’s somewhat of a moron, who fails at his own speciality, neuroscience. Can Sam, himself, be considered to have an irrational fear of Muslims, or anything Islamic?

On the one hand, Sam does sometimes differentiate between Jihadists, Islamists, Muslims, etc., in some of his writing. On the other hand, he sometimes doesn’t differentiate very well, and does some broad brushing. Where Sam seems to have the biggest problem, as many other people do, is differentiating between a religion and a holy book. A book is not a religion.

“My honest view is that Islam is not a religion of war or of peace – it’s a religion. Its sacred scripture, like those of other religions, contains passages that many people would consider extremely problematic. Likewise, all scriptures contain passages that are innocuous. Religion doesn’t inherently speak for itself; no scripture, no book, no piece of writing has its own voice. I subscribe to this view whether I’m interpreting Shakespeare or interpreting religious scripture.” ~ Maajid Nawaz

A religion is a belief system practised by an individual, or a group of individuals. To get from point A (book) to point B (religion), you need people. In this case, specifically Muslims. To say that “Islam is the mother load of bad ideas” amounts to saying that Muslims came up with “the mother load of bad ideas”. For “Islam”, itself, to be “the mother load of bad ideas” would mean that what all Muslims are practising is a religion that is “the mother load of bad ideas”. You can see how this could be taken as a somewhat irrational generalization, that might get someone labelled a bigot, Islamophobe, or what not.

It seems somewhat ironic that non-believers have been pointing out contradictions in religious texts, for centuries, yet now we have some coming along and claiming there is one correct way to interpret those religious writings. Even more ironic, is that he helps promote the extremists’ interpretation of Islam as being the correct form of Islam, rather than promoting the most moderate interpretation possible. Sam actually helps Islamists and Jihadists argue that theirs is the “true” Islam, while complaining about imaginary “regressive leftists” that he strawmans, claiming they are the ones who support Islamists, simply because they criticize him.

Constantly expressing his interpretation of the Qur’an as the true correct Islam would suggest that we should be afraid of every Muslim. Whether, or not, he has the phobia himself (I think he does), Sam sure as hell does his best to help spread irrational fear.

Sam admits that anti-Muslim bigotry is a thing, while claiming Islamophobia is not a thing. The problem here is that, if you take the Islam out of the Muslim, they’re no longer Muslim. The actual irrational fear is that all Muslims follow the exact same worst interpretation of Islam that you can think of. Sam definitely helps spread that irrational fear around.

Let’s take a look at a few examples from history, as analogies.

Firstly, at a specific point in history, we could say that almost all Japanese people on the planet were following an ideology that wanted to see the fall of the Western world. Now, even though there was such a large percentage of Japanese people in the world against us, was it right to spread fear of all Japanese people? Was it right to start fearing the Japanese people living in our own countries? Even Dr. Seuss got in on the propaganda.

drseussjapan1

Taking that path, down the road of fear, led to us treating Japanese citizens absolutely horribly. Now, I know Sam’s version of utilitarian morality allows for torture, so he may think this was a reasonable course of action, but I think it was a deplorable way to treat our own citizens. Some of them were even vets of WWI who had clearly shown loyalty to their country. Even at that point in history where you might have been able to say that the majority of Japanese people in the world were against us, punishing those who did no wrong was, in my opinion, immoral. Of course, my morality is only subjective, or relative. I don’t have “objective” morality, on my side, like Sam (that’ll be Part 2).

Another point in history we can look at is the early years of the Cold War. Even if one could say that the USSR, and their brand of communism, were some kind of threat to the United States, an irrational fear of everything to do with socialism/communism led to treating people horribly. People were spied on by the government, encouraged to spy on each other, people were blacklisted, interrogated, imprisoned, banished, etc. It was a terrible way to treat people.

america-under-communism

Not only did it lead to people turning on each other, but it led to bomb shelters, and a constant state of fear of nuclear war. It was emotional abuse, for the government to bombard people with so much fear, and hate, mongering.

I’ll Godwin myself here, as I point to another example. The Nazi party took their fear of communism even further. Hitler blamed an entire religious group, Jews, for communism. This is very much comparable to blaming an entire religious group, Muslims, for religious extremism. Now, I’m not saying Sam is about to throw people into ovens, here. However, the 1920s and 1930s propaganda, put out by the Nazis, may not have seemed too bad to some people, at the time. They may have considered it rational criticism of the Jews. They may have considered some of it just harmless cartoons.

naziboycott

Those guys don’t even look as threatening as the first guys, above. Just a couple of smartly dressed fellows, no assault rifles, innocently boycotting Jewish establishments, expressing their freedom of speech, and handing out some flyers. No big deal.

So, what is Islam?

Islam is whatever the individual Muslim makes of it. If their version of Islam allows for other ideas, like secularism and democracy, to be incorporated into their world view, then their version of Islam is a more moderate interpretation. There are as many versions of Islam as there are Muslims.

Historically, Muslims have indeed allowed for other ideas to be incorporate into their beliefs, so have practised a more moderate form of Islam. Many of the problems we’re seeing today, in certain parts of the world, were results of our own (Western civilization) actions.

Syria, had a democratically elected government. They voted against an oil pipeline. The US backed a coup, to get them out. Iran, had a democratically elected Prime Minister. He wanted to nationalize Iran’s oil. The US and UK backed a coup, to get him out. These people are demonstrating, in favour of nationalizing the oil, in 1953, before the coup.

iran19532

Iraq had a populist leader, who had just overthrown the British puppet dictator. He was talking about nationalizing Iraq’s oil. The US backed a coup, to take him out, and install the Ba’ath party. When Saddam later also decided to nationalize Iraq’s oil, the US and Israel encouraged a Kurdish uprising. When their puppet Shah fell, the US then turned to help Saddam, who used Western weaponry against the Kurds, and then started a war with Iran.

In Afghanistan, a communist party, friendly to the USSR, ousted the Afghan King, and the US immediately started backing Jihadists, to help draw the USSR into their own Vietnam. Cabul, in the 1970s, before the Jihadists took over.

cabul1970s

Western interference started even earlier, with the break up of the Ottoman Empire. There was a reason why most Jews felt safer in a Muslim empire, and many Muslim countries, than they did in many Christian countries. The Ottoman Empire, the last Islamic Caliphate, treated them okay, for the most part. It had also legalized homosexuality. Plus, it provided women with rights they didn’t have in many Christian countries. The Ottoman Empire was fairly liberal, for its day, before it was carved up. It was, for the most part, on par with the rest of the world.

Now, imagine that you were trying to overthrow the United States and, in an effort to do that, you made a deal with a bunch of their ultra conservative, 2nd amendment worshipping, gun-toating, evangelical Christian, private militia types, to get them to help you. Then, after the war, you carve up the US and put those people in charge of various smaller countries. That is, basically, what happened with parts of the Ottoman Empire.

And, of course, there is what has happened in Palestine, which is too complicated to get into. Suffice to say, that there are some valid grievances on the Palestine side of the equation that often get overlooked.

The point being, that a more conservative, Islamist form of Islam, coming to power in many places, is not entirely the fault of Islam itself. Now, so I don’t get straw manned, I’m not saying that more radical extremist Muslims didn’t exist before Western interventions. I’m saying that, if you’re going to remove the moderates from power, and help suppress them when they’re not in power, then you’re helping create a more ultra-conservative environment, where radical Islam becomes more dominant.

Every situation should be evaluated on its own. Blanket statements about how horrible Islam is, aren’t very helpful. It is not helpful to support women by telling any oppressive rulers that they are practising the correct form of Islam. It is not helpful to tell the women that any oppression or mistreatment they’re experiencing is the fault of their own religious beliefs. Tossing groups like Hezbollah in with groups like Al Qaeda, and talking about them as if they’re the same thing, also not helpful, and fairly dishonest. Especially in, and around, Israel, there are some valid grievances that need addressing.

Like the Qur’an, there are many violent passages in both the Bible and the Tanakh. However, Quakers are Christians who practise Christianity. To argue that the real Christianity is itself inherently violent would mean that Quakers couldn’t be real Christians. The same goes for Islam. To argue that the real Islam is itself inherently violent would mean that moderate Muslims couldn’t be real Muslims. This makes for the No True Scotsman argument put out by many.

What is “agnosticism”?

Those who promote “atheism” as a-theism also have a tendency to promote “agnosticism” as a-gnosticism. This makes “agnosticism” everything that is not pure gnosticism and makes it compatible with having beliefs. Again, these atheists are reconstructing words. “Agnosticism” comes from the Greek word “agnostos”. That is the root word, with the a- already permanently attached, and -ic and -ism suffixes added.

agnostos = no/not/without knowledge

ic = someone who is

ism = a belief system or doctrine

What did Huxley mean by “someone who is without knowledge”? He clearly defined it as a form of demarcation. No testable objective evidence = an unfalsifiable subjective claim. Results: inconclusive, no belief either way. Karl Popper, who also self-identified as an agnostic, cemented this line of thinking into the scientific method. This is “I don’t know”, as in a complete lack of certainty, not “I don’t know”, as in a lack of complete certainty.

Agnosticism is of the essence of science, whether ancient or modern. It simply means that a man shall not say he knows or believes that which he has no scientific grounds for professing to know or believe.

That which Agnostics deny and repudiate, as immoral, is the contrary doctrine, that there are propositions which men ought to believe, without logically satisfactory evidence; and that reprobation ought to attach to the profession of disbelief in such inadequately supported propositions.

Still speaking for myself, I add, that though Agnosticism is not, and cannot be, a creed, except in so far as its general principle is concerned; yet that the application of that principle results in the denial of, or the suspension of judgment concerning, a number of propositions respecting which our contemporary ecclesiastical “gnostics” profess entire certainty.

The extent of the region of the uncertain, the number of the problems the investigation of which ends in a verdict of not proven, will vary according to the knowledge and the intellectual habits of the individual Agnostic. I do not very much care to speak of anything as “unknowable.” What I am sure about is that there are many topics about which I know nothing; and which, so far as I can see, are out of reach of my faculties. But whether these things are knowable by any one else is exactly one of those matters which is beyond my knowledge, though I may have a tolerably strong opinion as to the probabilities of the case. Relatively to myself, I am quite sure that the region of uncertainty–the nebulous country in which words play the part of realities –is far more extensive than I could wish.

Huxley’s agnosticism clearly covers the question of belief, and positive disbelief, not just knowledge. He outright stated he thought it immoral to form a belief, without evidence to support said belief. He outright stated it was a suspension of judgement. His agnosticism was very clearly not compatible with theism, nor the narrow definition atheism of the time.

Theism and Atheism; the doctrine of the soul and its mortality or immortality–appear in the history of philosophy like the shades of Scandinavian heroes, eternally slaying one another and eternally coming to life again in a metaphysical “Nifelheim.” It is getting on for twenty-five centuries, at least, since mankind began seriously to give their minds to these topics. Generation after generation, philosophy has been doomed to roll the stone uphill; and, just as all the world swore it was at the top, down it has rolled to the bottom again. All this is written in innumerable books; and he who will toil through them will discover that the stone is just where it was when the work began. Hume saw this; Kant saw it; since their time, more and more eyes have been cleansed of the films which prevented them from seeing it; until now the weight and number of those who refuse to be the prey of verbal mystifications has begun to tell in practical life.

What is “atheism”?: Word Reconstruction

Root words are supposed to be the smallest base word, with all the suffixes and prefixes removed. The definition of the root word is supposed to be maintained, and is the base for any new words created by adding suffixes and prefixes.

The suffix -ist = a person with a particular set of beliefs or way of behaving.

The root word for theist is theos (god). Attaching the suffix -ist defines a person. Literally, a person who believes “god”, is true.

The prefix a- = without, no, or not.

The root word for “atheist” is still stated to be the Greek word “atheos” (no/not/without god). Maintaining the root word, and attaching the suffix -ist defines a person. Literally, a person who believes “no/not/without god”, is true.

When we turn to talk about “theism” and “atheism”, then we have swapped out the -ist suffix, for an -ism suffix, while maintaining the root words.

Well, okay then. What does a-theist mean? It literally means “not a god believer”. To attach an a- prefix, the new root word, for this new definition of “atheist”, should actually be “theist”. And, instead of swapping out the suffix to discuss “atheism”, we’re actually discussing a something with a different root word. The root for “a-theism” would be “theism”.

Because personhood is attached to the -ist suffix, and an a-theist isn’t an -ist, this word has not defined a person. A rock is “not a god believer”. It has also not created a philosophy that people are following. Unlike athe(os)-ism, which described a philosophy, a belief that we are without gods, a-theism, “no/not/without” “god belief” describes every non-sentient thing in existence, and most of the sentient ones, as well.

To make a-theist describe a person, you have to rip the personhood out of the “ist” suffix and transfer it to the “a” prefix, so that “a”= “someone without” and “theist” = “god belief”. Wait a minute, though, “theism” = “god belief”. Now the “theist” in a-theist and the “theism” in a-theism mean exactly the same thing, and “a” sometimes includes personhood and sometimes doesn’t. Either that, or “atheist” and “atheism” mean the same thing.

Broad definition atheist supporters argue for the word to be constructed like no other similar word. Many compare it to the word “amoral”. The problem there is that there are such things as amoral-ists and amoral-ism. “Amorlaist” means “someone who believes we are without morals”. “Amoralist” doesn’t mean”not a moralist”.

What is “atheism”?: Etymology

16th Century

An Athe(os)-ist is someone who believes that gods do not exist. In the 1570s, the French pulled the word “atheos” (no/not/without gods) out of Greek antiquity and added the suffix, “iste” (someone who believes, a believer), which became “someone who believes no gods exist”. The English followed suit.

atheist (n.)
1570s, from French athéiste (16c.), from Greek atheos “without god, denying the gods; abandoned of the gods; godless, ungodly,” from a- “without” + theos “a god” (see theo-).

John Florio, A World of Words (1598)
Atèo, Atheo, Atheista, an atheist, a miscreant, godles, one that thinkes there is no god.

17th Century

Randle Cotgrave, A Dictionary of the French and English Tongues (1611)
Athée: m. An Atheist; one that beleeues there is no God.

John Bullokar, An English Expositor (1616)
Atheist. He that wickedly beleeueth there is no God, or no rule of Religion.

Henry Cockeram, English Dictionary (1623)
Atheist. That thinks there is no God, or rule of religion.

Thomas Blount, Glossographia or a Dictionary (1656)
Atheist ( from the Gr ἄδεος. id est Sine Deo, godless) he that beleeves there is no God or rule of Religion, and that the soul dies with the body.

theist (n.)
1660s, from Greek theos “god” (see theo-) + -ist. The original senses was that later reserved to deist: “one who believes in a transcendent god but denies revelation.” Later in 18c. theist was contrasted with deist, as believing in a personal God and allowing the possibility of revelation.

^The word “theist” finally came into existence. The English pulled the word “theos” (god) out of Greek antiquity and added the suffix, “ist” (someone who believes, a believer), which became “someone who believes god exist”. Prior to this, for almost a full century, there was no word “theist” to attach an “a” prefix to.

18th Century

John Kersey the younger, A New English Dictionary (1702)
Atheism, the Opinion of
An Atheist, who denies the Being of a God.

An Universal Etymological English Dictionary, Nathan Bailey, R. Ware, 1756
ATHEIST (from Gr. without God) one that denies the exiftence of God.

A dictionary of the English language., Samuel Johnson, 1768
A’the-ist, f. One that denies the existence of a God.

19th Century

A primary-school pronouncing dictionary of the English language, Noah Webster, William Greenleaf Webster, J.B. Lippincott & Co., 1857
A’the-ist, n. one who denies the existence of a God.

Atheism in pagan antiquity by Drachmann, A. B. (Anders Björn), 1860-1935

ATHEISM and atheist are words formed from Greek roots and with Greek derivative endings. Nevertheless they are not Greek ; their formation is not consonant with Greek usage. In Greek they said atheos and atheotes ; to these the English words ungodly and ungodliness correspond rather closely. In exactly the same way as ungodly, atheos was used as an expression of severe censure and moral condemnation ; this use is an old one, and the oldest that can be traced. Not till later do we find it employed to denote a certain philosophical creed ; we even meet with philosophers bearing atheos as a regular surname. We know very little of the men in question ; but it can hardly be doubted that atheos, as applied to them, implied not only a denial of the gods of popular belief, but a denial of gods in the widest sense of the word, or Atheism as it is nowadays understood.

20th Century

Atheism: The Case Against God, by George H Smith, 1973

“First, there is the familiar sense in which a person is an atheist if he maintains that there is no God, where this is taken to mean that “God exists” expresses a false proposition. Secondly, there is also a broader sense in which a person is an atheist if he rejects belief in God, regardless of whether his rejection is based on the view that belief in God is false.”
“This immediately raises the question of agnosticism, which has traditionally been offered as a third alternative to theism and atheism.”
“An agnostic is not an atheist. An atheist denies the existence of God; an agnostic professes ignorance about His existence. For the latter, God may exist, but reason can neither prove nor disprove it.”
“Notice that agnosticism emerges as a third alternative only if atheism is narrowly defined as the denial of theism.”

The Presumption of Atheism, by Antony Flew, 1984

In this interpretation an atheist becomes: not someone who positively asserts the non-existence of God; but someone who is simply not a theist. Let us, for future ready reference, introduce the labels ‘positive atheist’ for the former and ‘negative atheist’ for the latter.
The introduction of this new interpretation of the word ‘atheism’ may appear to be a piece of perverse Humpty-Dumptyism, going arbitrarily against established common usage. ‘Whyever’, it could be asked, ‘don’t you make it not the presumption of atheism but the presumption of agnosticism?’

21st Century

Now, although a broader definition has gained some popularity over the past 30 years, it is still not the only definition. The narrow definition is still usually included, and the broader definition is still sometimes not included. The broad definition is most popular in atheist circles.

“one who believes that there is no deity”

“a person who believes that God does not exist”

“someone who believes that God does not exist”

“a person who believes that God does not exist”

“someone who believes that God does not exist”

“one who believes that there is no God or gods.”

“someone who denies the existence of god”

SEXTUS EMPERICUS

Outlines of Pyrrhonism

” If one defines a system as an attachment to a number of dogmas that agree with one another and with appearances, and defines a dogma as an assent to something non-evident, we shall say that the Skeptic does not have a system. But if one says that a system is a way of life that, in accordance with appearances, follows a certain rationale, where that rationale shows how it is possible to seem to live rightly (“rightly” being taken, not as referring only to virtue, but in a more ordinary sense) and tends to produce the disposition to suspend judgment, then we say that he does have a system.”

“Let the Dogmatists first agree and concur with one another that god is such and such, and only then, when they have sketched this out for us, let them expect us to form a concept of god. But as long as they do not settle their disagreements we cannot tell what agreed-upon conception we are supposed to get from them.”

“Furthermore, if we go by what the Dogmatists say, even if we form a conception of god it is necessary to suspend judgment concerning whether he exists or does not exist. For it is not pre-evident that god exists.”

“Further, even if someone should grant that it is possible to form a concept of cause, because of the disagreement it would be considered not to be apprehensible. For some say that there are examples of causation, some say that there are not, and some suspend judgment.”

“From these points we conclude further that if the arguments by which we show the existence of causes are plausible, and if those, too, are plausible which prove that it is incorrect to assert the existence of a cause, and if there is no way to give preference to any of these over others – since we have no agreed-upon sign, criterion, or proof, as has been pointed out earlier – then, if we go by the statements of the Dogmatists, it is necessary to suspend judgment about the existence of causes, too, saying that they are “no more” existent than non-existent.”

DAVID HUME

“That Prince of Agnostics, David Hume” ~ T H Huxley

 Hume, with Helps to the study of Berkeley, by Thomas H Huxley

“He said he never had entertained any belief in Religion since he began to read Locke and Clarke. I asked him if he was not religious when he was young. He said he was. . . . He then said flatly that the Morality of every Religion was bad, and, I really thought, was not jocular when he said ‘that when he heard a man was religious, he concluded he was a rascal, though he had known some instances of very good men being religious.’” ~ James Boswell

The Natural History of Religion

The whole is a riddle, an enigma, an inexplicable mystery. Doubt, uncertainty, suspense of judgment, appear the only result of our most accurate scrutiny concerning this subject. But such is the frailty of human reason, and such the irresistible contagion of opinion, that even this deliberate doubt could scarcely be upheld, did we not enlarge our view, and, opposing one species of superstition to another, set them a quarrelling; while we ourselves, during their fury and contention, happily make our escape into the calm, though obscure, regions of philosophy.

The Reception of David Hume In Europe

According to Diderot, as recorded in a letter to his mistress, Sophie Volland, 6 October 1765… The first time that M. Hume found himself at the table of the Baron, he was seated beside him. I don’t know for what purpose the English philosopher took it into his head to remark to the Baron that he did not believe in atheists, that he had never seen any. The Baron said to him: “Count how many we are here.” We are eighteen. The Baron added: “It isn’t too bad a showing to be able to point out to you fifteen at once: the three others haven’t made up their minds.”

Create a free website or blog at WordPress.com.

Up ↑